PUBLICATIONS

  • ABSTRACT | LINK

    In recent years, there has been a revival of interest in genealogy among social and political philosophers. I argue, however, that this growing literature has tended to obscure what distinguishes genealogy as an approach to the interpretation of history. Any normative evaluation of something that appeals to an account of its origins has come to be called a “genealogy,” even if this account is explicitly hypothetical or unabashedly teleological. But a genealogy, according to Friedrich Nietzsche and Michel Foucault, is not merely an account of origins: it is an account of the contingent origins of the integration of an institution, practice, or concept within a regime of power and control. In other words, genealogy investigates an institution, practice, or concept through the lens of what Nietzsche calls “the will to power.” This paper aims to reconstruct the conception of the will to power Foucault inherits from Nietzsche in a way that explains why investigations into struggles for power from the past can provide insight into the strategies used for exercising and maintaining power in the present. The critical contribution of genealogy, I argue, is not normative insight but tactical knowledge: to oppose something successfully, first you must know your enemy.

WORKS IN PROGRESS

  • ABSTRACT

    This paper argues for understanding the systems of power investigated by Michel Foucault as “machines” in the idiosyncratic sense of this term developed by Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari. These systems are called “dispositifs” by Foucault, and each is made up of a heterogenous collection of elements, such as institutions, techniques, procedures, and discourses, that co-operate in the exercise of power over a phenomenon such as crime, disease, reproduction, or education. Although there are many reasons for believing that Deleuze and Guattari’s conception of machines was an important influence on Foucault’s thinking about systems of power, the relationship between the concept of the dispositif and the concept of the machine remains obscure. I argue that Deleuze and Guattari’s conception of machines provides a model for the emergence of functionality in a system of power that is crucial for Foucault’s understanding of dispositifs. For functionality to be “emergent” is for it to arise in large part through contingency and chance, rather than through the designs of technocrats or the scheming of elites. By reconciling the study of systemic power with the acknowledgement of historical contingency, I argue the concept of the machine is at the center of a project common to Foucault, Deleuze, and Guattari that I call “Nietzschean functionalism.”

  • ABSTRACT

    This paper provides a reconstruction of Michel Foucault’s conception of systemic power that defends it against objections made by Charles Taylor, Jürgen Habermas, Axel Honneth, and others. These objections identify a central tension in Foucault’s view: although he maintains that power is not possessed by individuals but put into operation by governmental systems (i.e. “dispositifs”), he claims it is exercised in accordance with strategies for the exercise of mastery and control. But how can a “system” undertake a “strategy” if that strategy is not consciously arranged or centrally coordinated by any individual or group? In homage to Hegel’s doctrine of “the cunning of reason,” I call the view that systems of power exhibit a strategic rationality not reducible to the rationality of individuals “the cunning of power.” This article shows that by conceiving dispositifs as “technological” in Martin Heidegger’s sense, Foucault provides a compelling account of how bodies of knowledge concerning objects such as crime, disease, and terror can act as a mechanism for the coordination of strategies of mastery and control even in the absence of any conscious coordination or central planning, i.e. that “the cunning of power” is at work in “the will to knowledge.”

  • ABSTRACT

    This paper analyzes Michel Foucault’s conception of resistance, revolt, and uprising through the lens of Georges Bataille’s conception of “excess.” Critics of Foucault have often leveled the charge that his investigations of power fail to show in what ways regimes of power can be opposed or resisted. At best, these critics argue, resistance is a topic that is underexplored and underthematized in Foucault’s writings. At worst, Foucault is said to conceive of power as having such a totalizing hold and pervasive presence in any social order that resistance becomes altogether inconceivable. These criticisms imply a stark rejection of Foucault’s own understanding of his work, since he often claims his analysis implies that resistance to power is as prevalent and even more fundamental than power itself. This paper seeks to reconstruct the conception of resistance that Foucault means to invoke in making this claim by showing his debt to the thought of Bataille. “Excess” is a functional notion in Bataille’s thinking, i.e. a behavior is an example of “excess” only if it resists integration into the normal functioning of a social order due to its violent or disruptive character. Eroticism, for instance, is fundamentally linked to excess since, in Bataille’s view, it is a form of sexual urge aroused precisely by the allure of violating and disrupting everyday taboos. I argue that for Foucault “resistance,” which occasionally expands into large-scale revolts and uprisings against a regime of power, initially consists in “excessive” behaviors that the regime is unable to functionally integrate or accommodate.

DISSERTATION

  • ABSTRACT | LINK

    This dissertation addresses a challenge facing Michel Foucault’s conception of systemic power, a challenge I call “the problem of organization.” Foucault argues that power is exercised through systems (dispositifs) that are made up of various elements, such as institutions, procedures, techniques, and discourses, that co-operate in the execution of strategies of mastery and control. However, this view gives rise to a question: What accounts for the organization in purpose and function exhibited by systems of power, such as the criminal justice system or the public health apparatus, if the strategies they put into operation are not consciously arranged or centrally coordinated by any specific person or group? I argue that Foucault answers this challenge by conceiving such systems as technological, drawing on accounts of technology found in the work of Georges Canguilhem, Martin Heidegger, and Friedrich Nietzsche. Foucault holds that this organization emerges not in accordance with a conscious plan, as in a conspiracy, nor through an evolutionary process, as in an organism, but instead, like in a technology, through the decentralized coordination made possible by the production and circulation of knowledge.